Inspired by this question: Are these two quantum systems distinguishable? and discussion therein.
Given an ensemble of states, the randomness of a measurement outcome can be due to classical reasons (classical probability distribution of states in ensemble) and quantum reasons (an individual state can have a superposition of states). Because a classical system cannot be in a superposition of states, and in principle the state can be directly measured, the probability distribution is directly measurable. So any differing probability distributions are distinguishable. However in quantum mechanics, an infinite number of different ensembles can have the same density matrix.
What assumptions are necessary to show that if two ensembles initially have the same density matrix, that there is no way to apply the same procedure to both ensembles and achieve different density matrices? (ie. that the 'redundant' information regarding what part of Hilbert space is represented in the ensemble is never retrievable even in principle)
To relate to the referenced question, for example if we could generate an interaction that evolved:
1) an ensemble of states $|0\rangle + e^{i\theta}|1\rangle$ with a uniform distribution in $\theta$
to
2) an ensemble of states $|0\rangle + e^{i\phi}|1\rangle$ with a non-uniform distribution in $\phi$
such an mapping of vectors in Hilbert space can be 1-to-1. But it doesn't appear it can be done with a linear operator.
So it hints that we can probably prove an answer to the question using only the assumption that states are vectors in a Hilbert space, and the evolution is a linear operator.
Can someone list a simple proof showing that two ensembles with initially the same density matrix, can never evolve to two different density matrices? Please be explicit with what assumptions you make.
Update: I guess to prove they are indistinguishable, we'd also need to show that non-unitary evolution like the projection from a measurement, can't eventually allow one to distinguish the underlying ensemble either. Such as perhaps using correlation between multiple measurements or possibly instead of asking something with only two answers, asking something with more that two so that finally the distribution of answers needs more than just the expectation value to characterize the results.
Answer
You only need to assume
- the Schrödinger equation (yes, the same old linear Schrödinger equation, so the proof doesn't work for weird nonlinear quantum-mechanics-like theories)
- the standard assumptions about projective measurements (i.e. the Born rule and the assumption that after you measure a system it gets projected into the eigenspace corresponding to the eigenvalue you measured)
Then it's easy to show that the evolution of a quantum system depends only on its density matrix, so "different" ensembles with the same density matrix are not actually distinguishable.
First, you can derive from the Schrödinger equation a time evolution equation for the density matrix. This shows that if two ensembles have the same density matrix and they're just evolving unitarily, not being measured, then they will continue to have the same density matrix at all future times. The equation is $$\frac{d\rho}{dt} = \frac{1}{i\hbar} \left[ H, \rho \right]$$
Second, when you perform a measurement on an ensemble, the probability distribution of the measurment results depends only on the density matrix, and the density matrix after the measurement (of the whole ensemble, or of any sub-ensemble for which the measurement result was some specific value) only depends on the density matrix before the measurement.
Specifically, consider a general observable (assumed to have discrete spectrum for simplicity) represented by a hermitian operator $A$. Let the diagonalization of $A$ be $$A = \sum_i a_i P_i$$ where $P_i$ is the projection operator in to the eigenspace corresponding to eigenvalue (measurement outcome) $a_i$. Then the probability that the measurement outcome is $a_i$ is $$p(a_i) = \operatorname{Tr}(\rho P_i)$$ This gives the complete probability distribution of $A$.
The density matrix of the full ensemble after the measurment is $$\rho' = \sum_i P_i \rho P_i$$ and the density matrix of the sub-ensemble for which the measurment value turned out to be $a_i$ is $$\rho'_i = \frac{P_i \rho P_i}{\operatorname{Tr}(\rho P_i)}$$
Since none of these equations depend on any property of the ensemble other than its density matrix (e.g. the pure states and probabilities of which the mixed state is "composed"), the density matrix is a full and complete description of the quantum state of the ensemble.
No comments:
Post a Comment