The state of a quantum system is represented by a wavefunction usually in some specific Hilbert space, .e.g of position, spin, momentum etc.
But before deciding in which of these bases to decompose the wavefunction in, what form does the wavefunction have? Of course not having decomposed it yet, it does not yet have a component-wise definition. To clarify with example, we write: $$|\psi(x)\rangle = \langle x|\psi\rangle|x\rangle$$ But what form does this mysterious $\psi$ have before the x-basis representation? How is the inner product above even allowed if $\psi$ is not yet defined in some other basis?
On a related note: does the Schrodinger equation have other representations other than its position and momentum forms? I mean e.g. can one obtain the spin wavefunction $\psi_S$ of a system directly from the Schrodinger equation? Or first $\psi_x$ is obtained and then decomposed in a spin basis?
A last question regarding the wavefunction for more than 1 dimension: When one writes $\psi(x,y)$ do $x$ and $y$ correspond to different Hilbert spaces $|x\rangle$ and $|y\rangle$? In which case we'd write $\psi(x,y) \in |x\rangle \otimes |y\rangle $ does this mean that a single particle in 2 dimensions looks very much like 2 particles each in one dimension? Or one should never mix multidimensionality with multi-body systems in QM?
Answer
Was typing this halfway through when Timaeus posted his answer. There is some overlap, but also some potentially useful additional details. Hope it helps.
- One fundamental assumption (axiom, postulate, principle, etc) of Quantum Mechanics is that the state of a system is represented by a state vector $|\psi \rangle$ in a unique Hilbert space ${\mathcal H}$ that is "rich enough" to comprise all possible states of the system. Note that a Hilbert space comes equipped with an inner product between its vectors, in this case the famed $\langle \phi | \psi \rangle$ for $|\phi\rangle, |\psi \rangle$ any two state vectors in ${\mathcal H}$. This answers your question about the usage of the inner product. As for the state vector, there is nothing else to "the form" of the state vector "before any decomposition". Think about it as a formal object that encapsulates all the information about the state of the system. The real deal is how we do the encapsulation and how we can use it to do some real physics. It sounds a bit circular, and we need to cut the Gordian knot. In QM this is done by defining observables, eigenvalues, and eigenstates, and characterizing the Hilbert space of states in terms of a complete set of observables and their common eigenstates. If it sounds very formal, it is. But it works.
So, before we get to the part on $\psi(x)$, we need to clarify the part about observables in general. The fundamental assumption of QM regarding observables is that every observable O is represented by a self-adjoint operator ${\hat O}$ on ${\mathcal H}$, that is ${\hat O}:{\mathcal H} \rightarrow {\mathcal H}$, ${\hat O} = {\hat O}^\dagger$. It is further postulated that the average value of O in any state $|\psi \rangle$ is given by the matrix element $\langle \psi | {\hat O} | \psi \rangle = \langle \psi | {\hat O} \psi \rangle$. The fact that ${\hat O}$ is postulated self-adjoint, has several dramatic consequences:
1) If ${\hat O}$ is self-adjoint, it is already implied that there exists in ${\mathcal H}$ a basis of eigenstates $|\omega \rangle$ of ${\hat O}$, for which ${\hat O}|\omega \rangle = \omega |\omega \rangle$.
2) If the $| \omega \rangle$-s form a basis, it follows that any state vector $|\psi \rangle$ can be expressed as a superposition $|\psi \rangle = \sum_{\omega} {c_\omega |\omega \rangle }$.
3) From the existence of decompositions $|\psi \rangle = \sum_{\omega} {c_\omega |\omega \rangle }$ it follows that for an arbitrary $|\psi \rangle$ the standard deviation associated to the average value of O on $|\psi \rangle$ is in general non-zero, $\langle \psi | (\Delta {\hat O})^2 | \psi \rangle = \langle \psi | {\hat O}^2 | \psi \rangle - \langle \psi | {\hat O} | \psi \rangle^2 ≠ 0$, but for the eigenstates of O we find $\langle \psi | (\Delta {\hat O})^2 | \psi \rangle = \omega^2 - \omega^2 = 0$. In other words, just from the self-adjointness of ${\hat O}$ we have that in any state $|\omega \rangle$ observable O has a well-defined, sharp value $\langle \omega | {\hat O} | \omega \rangle = \omega$.
4) Given the above, it follows further that two observables A and B cannot produce sharp values simultaneously unless their corresponding operators commute and admit a common set of eigenstates. It is not difficult to prove, but I will not go into details. Suffice it to emphasize that this is an expression of the uncertainty principle and everything follows from the mere self-adjointness of observables on the Hilbert space ${\mathcal H}$.
Now, how does this help us with the $\psi(x)$ problem and everything? It is actually the crux of it, since the Hilbert space of states ${\mathcal H}$ is always defined in terms of the system's degrees of freedom, which are nothing but a complete set of commuting observables. In general, if a system is completely characterized by degrees of freedom (or observables) $Q_1$, $Q_2$, ..., $Q_n$, then each of its states is necessarily labeled by a corresponding set of values $\{q_1, q_2, ..., q_n \}$ that can be measured simultaneously. According to the fundamental assumptions of QM, this means that $Q_1$, $Q_2$, ..., $Q_n$ must necessarily be represented on ${\mathcal H}$ by mutually commuting self-adjoint operators ${\hat Q_1}$, ${\hat Q_2}$, ..., ${\hat Q_n}$ that admit a common set of eigenstates labeled by $\{q_1, q_2, ..., q_n \}$, say $|q_1, q_2, ..., q_n \rangle$. All is good so far, but how do we get such $|q_1, q_2, ..., q_n \rangle$ in the first place? Simple: we postulate them. There is literally nothing else that we can do. But once we do this, we are left with an airtight definition of the Hilbert space of states ${\mathcal H}$ and we can even do physics.
To get to the actual heart of the matter: Let's take a spinless particle on a 1D line. It has one degree of freedom, which we can take to be the position $x$ along the line. Observable $x$ must be represented in the Hilbert space of the particle by a self-adjoint operator ${\hat x}$ that generates a basis set $|x\rangle$. The states $|x \rangle$ must be states in which the particle is found with certainty at position $x$, such that ${\hat x} | x \rangle = x | x \rangle$. Conversely, if we postulate the states $|x \rangle$ as a basis set, we have defined ${\mathcal H}$. The important thing is that now any state $|\psi \rangle$ of the particle can be represented as a superposition
$$ | \psi \rangle = \int{dx\; \psi(x) |x \rangle}, \;\; \text{with}\;\;\psi(x) = \langle x | \psi \rangle $$
Of course, we can also define the Hilbert space in terms of the particle's momentum $p$ and obtain a similar decomposition in terms of momentum eigenstates $|p \rangle$. Is this Hilbert space different from the one before? No. Since the Hilbert space comprises all possible states of the particle, the momentum eigenstates $|p \rangle$ must admit a decomposition in terms of position eigenstates $|x \rangle$ and vice-versa. Once the plane-wave form of the wavefunction $\langle x | p \rangle$ is defined, all rules about decomposing a state as a superposition of basis states apply as before.
Are there other representations than position or momentum? Absolutely! Think energy eigenstates in the hydrogen atom. The bound states are labeled by energy, angular momentum, azimuthal angular momentum, and spin. The corresponding wave functions are decompositions in the position representation. However, the spin component comes as an additional degree of freedom, not from the Schroedinger equation itself. Once the existence of spin is acknowledged, the Hilbert space is extended to account for spin states. And this brings us to the last question.
The essence of your question is: given a Hilbert space for a certain number of degrees of freedom, how is it extended if we need to account for additional degrees of freedom? Take for instance the 1D particle. What if the particle has spin? It obviously keeps the $x$ degree of freedom, but we need to account in addition for the spin degree of freedom. We can build new states $|x, \sigma \rangle$ that locate a particle with spin $\sigma$ (along some given direction) at position $x$, rebuild the Hilbert space, and think about $x$ and $\sigma$ as labels, the way Timaeus suggested. But the reality is that the Hilbert space so extended is isomorphic to the direct product of the spinless Hilbert space by a new Hilbert space corresponding to the spin degree of freedom. In fact, the direct product form is the preferred one for a variety of reasons. This is why we can and do commonly write something like $|\Psi \rangle = |\psi \rangle \otimes |\sigma \rangle$, where $|\psi \rangle$ is a spinless state vector.
So can we think the same way about spatial degrees of freedom like $x$ and $y$? Formally yes. Although you can view $x$ and $y$ as labels for a 2D particle, there is also an isomorphism with a system of two distinguishable 1D particles. Similarly, a system of two distinguishable 3D particles is isomorphic to one particle living in a 6D configuration space. But unlike for spin, it is commonly more convenient to use the label view, especially when dealing with coordinate changes to curvilinear coordinates. The isomorphism is still there, but is not invoked.
Additional info based on comments:
Are Hilbert spaces for different degrees of freedom (DOFs) isomorphic? If so, don't we need just one copy in the total Hilbert space? The Hilbert spaces corresponding to dissimilar DOFs, like position and spin, may have very different cardinality (dimension) and thus need not be isomorphic to each other. In general, even if some DOFs do generate formally isomorphic Hilbert spaces, like the $x$ and $y$ coordinates, the total Hilbert space of the system must account for each DOF individually. It is always a direct product of the Hilbert spaces for each of the DOFs. For a 1D particle with spin, it is ${\mathcal H}_x \otimes {\mathcal H}_\sigma$. For a 2D particle with spin, it is ${\mathcal H}_x \otimes {\mathcal H}_y \otimes {\mathcal H}_\sigma$ or ${\mathcal H}_{x,y} \otimes {\mathcal H}_\sigma$, but no longer just ${\mathcal H}_x \otimes {\mathcal H}_\sigma$.
How do we account for non-commuting observables? Take $x$ and $p$ for the 1D particle. There are no common $|xp \rangle$ eigenstates ($[x,p] ≠0$), but the spinless ${\mathcal H}$ is completely characterized by means of either the $\{ |x \rangle \}$ or the $\{ |p \rangle \}$ basis. Since ${\mathcal H}$ must contain all possible (spinless) states, if we choose the $\{ |x \rangle \}$ basis then we must express the $ |p \rangle $ states in terms of the $ |x \rangle $ states, and conversely. This is done by specifying the (canonical) commutation relation between $x$ and $p$, $[x, p] = i\hbar$, which leads to an expression for the momentum wave functions $\langle x | p \rangle$.
For a complete set of commuting observables, why do we keep only the common eigenstates? This is simply because the "common eigenstates" include all the eigenstates for the every observable in the complete set. In other words, given any observable ${\hat O}$ from the complete set, there are no eigenstates of ${\hat O}$ that are not in the set of "common eigenstates". For an observable ${\hat A}$ that is not among those in the complete set, the situation depends on whether it commutes or not with those in the complete set, but the result is the same. If it commutes with the entire set (think any $f({\hat O})$ ), its eigenstates are still those of the complete set. If it doesn't commute, (at least some of) its eigenstates are not in the set's common eigenstates, but can always be expressed as superpositions of those common eigenstates.
No comments:
Post a Comment