In Chapter 5 to "The Quantum Theory of Fields" by Weinberg he gives a nice point of view on antiparticles. He says the following (I've called the last equation (*) because it is not numbered in Weinberg's book):
It may be that the particles that are destroyed and created by these fields carry non-zero values of one or more conserved quantum numbers like the electric charge. For instance, if particles of species n carry a value q(n) for the electric charge Q, then [Q,a(p,σ,n)]=−q(n)a(p,σ,n),[Q,a†(p,σ,n)]=q(n)a†(p,σ,n).
In order that H(x) should commute with the charge operator Q (or some other symmetry generator) it is necessary that it be formed out of fields that have simple commutation relations with Q: [Q,ψℓ(x)]=−qℓψℓ(x)for then we can make H(x) commute with Q by constructing it as a sum of products of fields ψℓ1ψℓ2⋯ and adjoints ψ†m1ψ†m2⋯ such that qℓ1+qℓ2+⋯−qm1−qm2−⋯=0.
That this is sufficient I understand. Construct H(x) as H(x)=∑NM∑ℓ1⋯ℓN∑ˉℓ1⋯ˉℓMgℓ1⋯ℓNˉℓ1⋯¯ℓMψℓ1(x)⋯ψℓN(x)ψ†ˉℓ1(x)⋯ψ†ˉℓM(x).
Then we can show that (omitting the argument x to simply the notation): [Q,ψℓ1⋯ψℓNψ†ˉℓ1⋯ψ†ˉℓM]=(N∑i=1ψℓ1⋯ψℓi−1[Q,ψℓi]ψℓi+1⋯ψℓN)ψ†ˉℓ1⋯ψ†¯ℓM+ψℓ1⋯ψℓN(M∑i=1ψ†ˉℓ1⋯ψ†ˉℓi−1[Q,ψ†ˉℓi]ψ†ˉℓi+1⋯ψ†¯ℓM)
Therefore it is clear that if (5.1.33) holds and (*) holds, [Q,H(x)]=0. This shows that (5.1.33) together with (*) is sufficient to ensure charge conservation.
But Weinberg speaks as if it were necessary. He says it himself that for Q to commute with H(x) it is necessary that H(x) be formed out of fields for which (5.1.33) holds.
Why is this true? I can't see how [Q,H(x)]=0 implies that the fields appearing in the construction of H(x) should satisfy (5.1.33) and (*).
Answer
Since Weinberg is, after all, a physics book rather than a book of rigorous math, I'm not convinced that one should attempt to understand "necessary" here in its rigorous logical meaning rather than a colloquial meaning. In any case, whether the Hamiltonian is "necessarily" formed from such fields is an ill-defined question to begin with:
Suppose we start with a Hamiltonian of the form suggested by Weinberg, with N fields ψi and M ψ†j with simple commutation relations. If we now "rotate in field space", replacing the fields ψi by fields ψ′i , where the latter are the result of rotating the N-vector of ψi by some angle, you can plug these into the Hamiltonian (probably making it very ugly) to obtain the Hamiltonian of a theory that is completely equivalent to our "theory of simple fields" from the beginning but has no such simple commutation relations.
Conversely, if we start from fields with non-simple relations but [H,Q]=0, then elementary representation theory for U(1) (the symmetry group of the charge numbers we are considering here) suggests that the vector space of fields must decompose into one-dimensional representations. Simply switch basis so that we use the basis vectors of these irreps as your fields and we have arrived at a formulation of the theory with simple commutation relations.
So if one reads Weinberg as "it is necessary that for a Hamiltonian that is the sums of products of fields that have conserved charges, a following choice of fields exists", then "necessary" is correct. If one reads him as "the only way to write down such a theory is with fields with simple commutation relations", then it's wrong.
This is completely analogous to changing coordinates on configuration space in non-field-theories. Consider a theory where x-momentum is conserved but y- and z-momenta are not. Then certainly no one would suggest that using (x,y,z)-coordinates rather than e.g. spherical coordinates is necessary to have a Hamiltonian where x-momentum is conserved - it's just a nicer choice of coordinates.
No comments:
Post a Comment